Gödel's Incompleteness Of ZKPs

Application of Gödel's Incompleteness On Zero Knowledge Proofs

Abstract

Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems and zero-knowledge proofs (ZKPs) both reveal fundamental limitations in formal systems and cryptographic protocols. Gödel's theorems establish that in any sufficiently powerful formal system, there exist true statements that cannot be proven within that system. Zero-knowledge proofs, in a parallel fashion, enable one party (the prover) to convince another party (the verifier) of the truth of a statement without revealing the proof itself. This paper explores the intersection of these concepts, demonstrating that just as Gödel's theorems highlight the existence of true but unprovable statements, ZKPs allow the validation of truths while keeping the proof hidden.

Overview

Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems are two fundamental theorems in mathematical logic that have profound implications for the limits of formal systems. Here is a concise explanation of these theorems as they pertain to proofs that may be proven but cannot be derived from the system:

  1. First Incompleteness Theorem:

    • Statement: In any consistent formal system that is capable of expressing elementary arithmetic, there exist propositions that are true but cannot be proven within the system.

    • Implication: This theorem reveals that no matter how comprehensive a formal system is, there will always be true statements about the natural numbers that the system cannot prove. In other words, there are mathematical truths that lie beyond the reach of formal proof within the system itself.

  2. Second Incompleteness Theorem:

    • Statement: No consistent system can prove its own consistency.

    • Implication: If a formal system can prove its own consistency, it is, in fact, inconsistent. This means that a system cannot use its own axioms and inference rules to demonstrate that no contradictions can be derived from them.

Application to Proofs That Cannot Be Derived from the System

Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems imply that within any sufficiently powerful formal system (such as Peano arithmetic), there exist statements (Gödel sentences) that are true but unprovable within the system. These theorems can be understood through the lens of proof and derivation as follows:

  • True but Unprovable Statements: There are certain statements ( G ) that, although true, cannot be derived using the axioms and rules of inference of the formal system. These statements ( G ) are constructed in such a way that if the system were to prove ( G ), it would lead to a contradiction, thus implying the system is inconsistent.

  • Gödel Sentence: For a formal system ( S ), Gödel constructed a specific statement ( G_S ) which essentially says, "This statement is not provable in ( S )." If ( G_S ) were provable in ( S ), ( S ) would be inconsistent because it would prove a statement that asserts its own unprovability.

Fundamental Statement

In essence, Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems demonstrate that there are intrinsic limitations to what can be achieved with formal mathematical systems. There are truths that exist outside the boundaries of formal derivation, illustrating that the scope of formal proofs is inherently limited. This challenges the notion that mathematics, or any formal system, can be completely understood and proven solely through its own rules and axioms.

Exploration

By examining scenarios such as the Hamiltonian cycle problem, we illustrate how ZKPs embody the principles of incompleteness, showing that some truths can be acknowledged without formal derivation or disclosure. This relationship underscores the deep connections between mathematical logic and cryptographic protocols, emphasizing the intertwined nature of provability and secrecy.

Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems are embodied in the concept of zero-knowledge proofs involving probability within a formal system and the properties of zero-knowledge proofs (ZKPs). Zero-knowledge proofs allow one party (the prover) to convince another party (the verifier) that a statement is true without revealing any information beyond the validity of the statement itself.

1. Zero-Knowledge Proofs (ZKPs) Overview

Zero-knowledge proofs are a type of cryptographic protocol that ensures the following properties:

  1. Completeness: If the statement is true, the honest verifier will be convinced of this fact by an honest prover.

  2. Soundness: If the statement is false, no cheating prover can convince the honest verifier that it is true, except with some small probability.

  3. Zero-Knowledge: If the statement is true, the verifier learns nothing other than the fact that the statement is true.

2. Application of Gödel's Incompleteness in Zero-Knowledge Proofs

Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems imply that within any sufficiently powerful formal system, there exist true statements that cannot be proven within the system. Applying this to zero-knowledge proofs, we can draw several parallels and insights:

  1. Undecidable Statements: Gödel's theorems show that there are true statements that cannot be proven within a system. Similarly, in the context of ZKPs, there might exist statements whose validity can be demonstrated to a verifier without providing a traditional proof that can be verified within a formal system. This means the verifier is convinced of the truth without accessing the actual proof, aligning with the concept that certain truths might be acknowledged without formal derivation.

  2. Proofs Beyond Formal Systems: In zero-knowledge proofs, the prover demonstrates the truth of a statement without revealing the proof itself. This mirrors Gödel's idea that certain truths exist beyond formal provability. A zero-knowledge proof ensures that the verifier is convinced of the statement's truth, much like how Gödel's theorems assure us of the existence of truths beyond formal systems, but without the verifier gaining knowledge about the underlying proof (which remains "undefined" or "hidden").

  3. Secrecy and Provability: Zero-knowledge proofs emphasize secrecy; the verifier learns nothing beyond the truth of the statement. This aligns with Gödel's concept that certain truths cannot be fully captured or derived within the system. The proof in a ZKP remains inaccessible (or "undefined") to the verifier, preserving its zero-knowledge nature, akin to how some true mathematical statements remain unprovable within their own systems.


3. Reductio ad Absurdum

is a classical method of argumentation used in logic and mathematics, which demonstrates that a proposition is true by showing that a false, contradictory, or absurd result follows from its denial. Essentially, it involves the following steps:1. Assume the Negation: Start by assuming that the proposition you want to prove is false. 2. Derive a Contradiction: Show that this assumption leads to a contradiction or an absurdity, something that is clearly false or logically inconsistent. 3. Conclude the Proposition: Since the assumption of the negation leads to a contradiction, conclude that the original proposition must be true.

Formal Structure

In formal terms, if you want to prove a proposition PP:

  1. Assume egPeg P (the negation of PP).

  2. Derive a contradiction CC (something that is obviously false, e.g., Q¬QQ \land \neg Q).

  3. Conclude PP since egPeg P leads to a contradiction.

Example

Let's apply reductio ad absurdum to prove that 2\sqrt{2} is irrational:

  1. Assume the Negation: Assume 2\sqrt{2} is rational, meaning it can be expressed as a fraction ab\frac{a}{b} where aa and bb are integers with no common factors.

  2. Derive a Contradiction:

    • 2=ab\sqrt{2} = \frac{a}{b} implies 2=a2b22 = \frac{a^2}{b^2}, so a2=2b2a^2 = 2b^2.

    • This means a2a^2 is even (since it is two times some integer), which implies aa must be even (since the square of an odd number is odd).

    • Let a=2ka = 2k for some integer kk. Then a2=(2k)2=4k2a^2 = (2k)^2 = 4k^2.

    • Substituting back, we get 4k2=2b24k^2 = 2b^2 or 2k2=b22k^2 = b^2. This means b2b^2 is also even, so bb must be even.

    • Since both aa and bb are even, they have a common factor of 2, contradicting our original assumption that ab\frac{a}{b} is in its simplest form.

  3. Conclude the Proposition: Since assuming 2\sqrt{2} is rational leads to a contradiction, 2\sqrt{2} must be irrational.

Reductio ad absurdum is a powerful tool in logic and mathematics, used to prove the validity of statements by demonstrating that their negation leads to untenable or contradictory conclusions.


4. ZKPs are Incomplete Gödel Statements

To define the incompleteness attribute of zero-knowledge proofs (ZKP) as an implementation of Gödel's Incompleteness, we illustrate how a statement can be true and accepted as true by a verifier without revealing the proof within the formal system.

Here's a concise primitive equation:

S( if SS then PZKPV:SQ without SQ)\forall S\left(\text { if } S \equiv S \text { then } P \rightarrow{ }^{Z K P} V: S \vDash Q \text { without } S \vdash Q\right)

Where:

SS is a statement.

Q\mathbf{Q} is the formal system.

SQS \vDash Q

means SS is true within the system QQ

SQS \vdash Q

means SS is provable within the system QQ

PP is the prover.

VV is the verifier.

PZKPVP \rightarrow{ }^{Z K P} V

indicates that the prover convinces the verifier using a zero-knowledge proof.

The equation states that if a statement SS is true in the system QQ, then the prover can convince the verifier of SS 's truth through a zero-knowledge proof, without SS being formally provable within QQ

5. Completeness

Let SS be a statement, PP be the prover, and VV be the verifier.

If SS is true, then an honest prover PP can convince the verifier VV of this fact.

If SS is true ightarrowPZKPVightarrow P \rightarrow{ }^{Z K P} V is convinced

6. Soundness

that SS is true, except with some small probability ϵ\epsilon

 If S is false PZKPV is convinced with probability ϵ\text { If } S \text { is false } \rightarrow P^{\prime} \rightarrow{ }^{Z K P} V \text { is convinced with probability } \epsilon

7. Zero-Knowledge

{If SS} is true, the verifier VV learns nothing other than the fact that SS is true.

If SS is true ightarrowVightarrow V learns SS is true and nothing else

8. A Scenario of ZKP/Gödel's Incompleteness

Consider a scenario where a prover wants to prove they know a solution to a complex mathematical problem (e.g., a Hamiltonian cycle in a large graph) without revealing the solution itself:

  • Gödel's Perspective: There might be a true statement about the graph (e.g., it has a Hamiltonian cycle) that cannot be proven within the formal system defining the graph's properties. This is analogous to the fact that the prover knows the Hamiltonian cycle exists (a true statement) but cannot derive (reveal) it within the zero-knowledge protocol.

  • Zero-Knowledge Proof: The prover uses a ZKP to convince the verifier that they know a Hamiltonian cycle without disclosing the cycle itself. The verifier becomes convinced of the truth (the graph has a Hamiltonian cycle) without learning the actual cycle (the proof remains undefined to the verifier).

Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems highlight the existence of true but unprovable statements within formal systems, paralleling the way zero-knowledge proofs allow one to demonstrate the truth of a statement without revealing the proof itself. This interplay underscores the philosophical and practical connections between mathematical logic and cryptographic protocols, showcasing how concepts of provability and secrecy intertwine in both fields.

To demonstrate how zero-knowledge proofs (ZKPs) can be considered incomplete in the context of Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems, we can represent the principles of ZKPs using mathematical formulations:

9. Incompleteness Example

Consider the scenario of proving the existence of a Hamiltonian cycle in a graph GG :

Let GG be a large graph, and let HH represent the Hamiltonian cycle within GG

The prover PP

knows HH

exists and wants to convince the verifier VV

without revealing HH

10. Gödel's Perspective Applied to ZKPs

In this context, Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems suggest the following:

True but Unprovable Statements: There exists a true statement about GG (e.g., it has a Hamiltonian cycle) that cannot be proven within the formal system of graph theory:

G\exists G : Hamiltonian (G) is true but not provable

Proof Beyond Formal Systems: The prover PP

can convince the verifier VV

of the truth of Hamiltonian (G)(G)

without revealing H:PZKPVH: P \rightarrow{ }^{Z K P} V : Hamiltonian (G)(G) is true

11. Mathematical Representation of ZKP Incompleteness

Hamiltonian Cycle Existence: Let Hamiltonian (G)(G) denote the existence of a Hamiltonian cycle in graph GG

If Hamiltonian (G)(G) is true ightarrowightarrow Prover PZKPP \rightarrow{ }^{Z K P} Verifier V is convinced

Gödel Sentence Analogy: There exists a Gödel sentence GSG_{S} stating, "This statement is not provable in the system." GSG_{S} : This statement is not provable ZKP Incompleteness: The prover PP knows the Hamiltonian cycle exists (true statement) but cannot provide a formal proof within the system (hidden proof):

PZKPV: Hamiltonian (G) is true without revealing the proof (cycle) itself P \rightarrow{ }^{Z K P} V: \text { Hamiltonian }(G) \text { is true without revealing the proof (cycle) itself }

Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems and zero-knowledge proofs share the idea that certain truths (or proofs) can exist and be acknowledged without being formally derived or revealed. The equations above capture this relationship, illustrating how ZKPs allow the verification of truths that remain hidden, resonating with the concept that some truths in formal systems are inherently unprovable.

12. Explicit Description

Example of a zero-knowledge proof (ZKP) corollary where Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems and zero-knowledge proofs is illustrated.

Here is a concise extraction with mathematical focus

Undecidable Statements and Gödel's Incompleteness: Gödel's theorems imply there exist true statements GG within a formal system SS that cannot be proven within SS. Let SS be a formal system capable of expressing elementary arithmetic.

There exists a statement GSG_{S} such that GSG_{S} is true, but SGSS \nvdash G_{S} (i.e., SS cannot prove GSG_{S} ). Zero-Knowledge Proofs (ZKPs) and Incompleteness:

In a ZKP, the prover PP aims to convince the verifier VV of the truth of a statement ϕ\phi without revealing the proof.

Completeness: If ϕ\phi is true, VV will be convinced by PP.

{ϕ\forall \phi (if ϕ\phi is true, then VV is convinced by PP )}

Soundness: If ϕ\phi is false, no cheating PP can convince VV that ϕ\phi is true, except with some small probability ϵ\epsilon

ϕ( ifϕisfalse, then(P)cannot convince(V)with probability>ϵ)\forall \phi( \ if \phi is false, \ then (P) cannot \ convince (V) with \ probability >\epsilon)

Zero-Knowledge: If ϕ\phi is true, VV learns nothing other than the fact that ϕ\phi is true.

Example: Hamiltonian Cycle in Graph Theory:

Let G=(V,E)G=(V, E) be a graph, and let HH be the statement "Graph GG has a Hamiltonian cycle."

Gödel's Perspective: HH may represent a true statement about the graph GG that cannot be proven within the formal system defining the properties of G.SHG . S \nvdash H, but HH is true.

Zero-Knowledge Proof: The prover PP knows a Hamiltonian cycle CC in G×PG \times P uses a ZKP to convince VV

that GG has a Hamiltonian cycle without revealing CC.

VV becomes convinced that HH is true without learning CC

13. Conclusion

Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems highlight the existence of true but unprovable statements within formal systems, paralleling the way zero-knowledge proofs allow one to demonstrate the truth of a statement without revealing the proof itself. The equations and concepts above illustrate the mathematical and logical connections between these two areas, showing how provability and secrecy are intertwined.

Last updated